The Ordeal of Willlessness
The Ordeal of Willlessness
OOC: Special thanks to Mirra Zanzibar, who after more than a year of
silence, we had a very long and very overdue chat. She described her month long
unspeaking as 'living without free will until her grief had passed'. Mirra has
a unique set of life experiences, leading her to profound and fundamental
understandings on various subjectmatter. Even though I have known her since we
were both kids, it is still like talking with someone from another planet. I
mean that in a good way. Many of our conversations are like talking with a
genuine alien entity, but it is very illuminating. Like so many of my
conversations with Mirra, there was voluminous required reading. My friends are
high maintenance that way, a small price to pay for having smart educated
friends with unique perspectives. I will spare you the thousands of pages of
near impossibly dense and dry academic philosophy and neurobiology journal
articles, I will however include the bibliography to anyone that was truly
serious to actually dare to read such extremely dry fare. You have been warned. A lot of the text
herein is borrowed heavily from Susan Blackmore, but modified for use as part
of explaining the Way of the Tau and Desertborn living. Susan Blackmore is a true genius,
I hope she would be understanding.
Free will is an intellectual
claim that relates to the myriad arguments that have raged over the centuries,
verily ever since the concept of free will was first posited.
Many people claim to live
one's life without free will, or as if one does not have free will is
impossible. A frequent claim is that if everyone lived this way morality and
the rule of law would collapse and all hell would break loose.
The kind of free will I am
discussing is the sort most ordinary people claim – a contra-causal kind of
free will, the idea that their thoughts or conscious decisions are the ultimate
cause of their actions and that those thoughts and decisions are free from
prior causes of their own.
Most people simply claim that
'I' decided to do it, or that 'my mind' or 'my thoughts' caused it to happen.
Very compelling, maybe considered common sense.
This is the common intuition
that underlies belief in free will, and there is plenty of research suggesting
that it is both false and misleading.
One line of research stems
from Libet's original work on the timing of voluntary actions (1985). This has
been amply replicated and deeply debated ever since. Another is the rapidly
developing neuroscience of volition which reveals the many areas in the
prefrontal cortex, supplementary motor area and parietal lobe which manage
decision making and impulse suppression (e.g. Haggard 2008). A third explores
the mechanisms involved when people come to believe that they did or did not
cause their own actions. This research, pioneered by Wegner (2002), shows that
the feeling that I did, or did not, do something is not proof of causation but
is a post-hoc attribution based on sequence, timing and other variables.
Despite all this knowledge,
the powerful feeling that 'I' can freely cause 'my' actions persists. if free
will is an illusion, it is one of the most successful and widespread illusions.
There is an inherent
difficulty of writing about self, we all refer to two different things in the
words, 'I' and 'my'. The first, 'I' is the fictional inner self who seems to be
a persisting entity with consciousness and free will: the second, 'my', is the
whole human being; a brain and body carrying out actions and being held, or not
held, responsible for them. The feeling of having free will amounts to the idea
that the inner self can freely cause the body to act.
Most people confidently claim
that they have, or are, a self, and that this self is a continuing and powerful
entity; it feels like a conscious agent who lives inside their body,
experiences their 'stream of consciousness' and is the one who decides what to
do. Without such an inner self, many people say, their life would have no
meaning. No wonder they are reluctant to give it up.
What we know about the brain,
even at the most basic level, appears incompatible with the existence of such
an entity. The human brain is a massively parallel system with decisions being
taken at multiple levels, at different rates, and in multiple parallel streams
all at once. Even though we may feel as though we are a continuous mental
entity who is the subject of our experiences and issues instructions from some
central command headquarters, there is no central place where this self could
live and no means by which it could interfere with all these different on-going
processes. In other words, we humans are clever decision-making machines that
are prone to a number of powerful illusions, in particular the illusion of a
persisting inner self that has consciousness and free will. Free will, in this
sense, is an illusion.
Proponents of many popular
compatibilist arguments often agree in rejecting contra-causal or magical free
will. Yet they seem to be trying, at all costs, to rescue some snippet of
freedom from the obvious fact that everything that happens in this universe is
either caused by something that went before or is a truly random event. Neither
of these alternatives provides any room for what most people would call free
will. Of course human beings make choices, there is no denying this. Nor am I
denying that we can be more or less constrained in the choices available to us,
nor that we can be held responsible for some choices and not others. But we
should not confuse the decision making powers of a living creature with freedom
of the will.
This has caused a lot of
confusion. Dennett's book "Freedom Evolves" is a wonderful
description of how humans and other animals have evolved the ability to make
ever more complex choices in ever more complex environments. But these choices
are not free in the sense that most people want them to be free. They are the
result of the evolved complexity of the perceptual and motor systems that
Dennett so ably describes. A more apt title would therefore be "Choice
Evolves".
The complexities of
philosophical discussion aside, the more challenging question is if there is no
free will, how should we live our lives?
There are two possible
responses: One is to go on living 'as if' we have free will – in other words,
to accept that free will is an illusion and yet choose to remain deluded (not a
free choice of course, but one caused by prior events and circumstances). The
other is to reject the illusion and aspire to live entirely without free will.
The first of these is by far
the more common.
Living "As if".
Almost everybody who's happy and healthy tends to do that. However, our sense
of being a conscious agent who does things comes at a cost of being technically
wrong all the time.
Our minds produce a sense of
virtual agency, the feeling that we are a self who does things. This ends up
being a very useful accounting system and a useful way of keeping apprised of
our actions as opposed to those of others, or of the world. The fact that the
sense of agency is illusory doesn't mean that it's any less important since it
still guides our subsequent behaviour. Humans evolved this way. In other words,
we should carry on living 'as if' we have free will because the illusion has
been useful for countless generations and we don't yet know how to be happy or
healthy without it.
The brain has this user
illusion – that your decisions are made according to, shall we say, the
standard model – that you consciously identify the options, you consciously do
an expected utility calculation, you consciously choose, and then at some point
later in time, the action's executed. That's a useful user illusion.
It's very useful for people to
have the illusion that these are really true.
Intellectually, I side with
Susan Blackmore that the user illusion is malign and we might be better to try
to throw it out and live without it.
There are some compelling
arguments that the illusion might be positively dangerous to give it up with
potentially terrible consequences. I think for most people most of the time,
you have to assume that other individuals are acting of their own free will,
and that you yourself are a cohesive entity.
But the arguments are faulty,
"if no one has free will, it means that no one should be in prison… how
can it provide a deterrent for people if they don't have free will; it's not up
to them."
Because of the strong
traditions of The Way of the Tau, most Desertborn technically do not ascribe
free will to their behaviors. A mere few thousands of years of philosophical thinking
is not enough to overcome millions of years of evolution.
One of the Desertborn’s blind
spots in this regard is our notions related to the criminal justice system
The criminal justice system is
stronger and fairer when not based on the notion of free will. When we disposed
of the idea of retribution; of punishing people because they acted badly of
their own free will and so deserve to suffer, our criminal justice system
became more effective. People are sent to prison for other reasons: to keep
them away from doing any more harm to others, for training or rehabilitation,
or as a deterrent to them or others in the future. We know that appropriate
rewards and punishments can change people's behaviour.
Mostly rehabilitation and
redemption is only for Desertborn, certainly for serious crimes, all others
only receive retribution based justice. This is patently unbalanced, although
the Elder Council insists it is a necessary deterrent for people who do not
identify themselves as part of our culture and brazenly act as parasites and
predators. We still suffer the scars from the Spice Wars.
Rehabilitation has its own
difficulties and challenges, which I shall discuss elsewhere. The Margrave
makes a particularly compelling argument regarding retribution over
rehabilitation. I found this surprising, because if he would convince the
Desertborn to give up retributive justice, we would probably kill fewer
offworlders.
The relevant question would
not be 'does this person deserve to be punished?', but would this punishment do
any good to them, to their victims, or to society in general.
Arguments of the 'my genes
made me do it' type or whatever become irrelevant if we agreed that every
action everyone carries out is caused by their genes, their memes, and the
environments they have lived in. Arguments of the 'I didn't know what I was
doing' type would not hinge on whether or not the person was really responsible
of his own free will, but on whether any punishment would be effective. For
those too young or mentally incapacitated the answer would often be 'no' and
there would be no point in putting them in prison, or that they were incurable
and had to be locked away forever. These are complex issues, but in principle
there is no credible reason to believe that society and its criminal justice
system would collapse and crime would run amok if we dropped the idea of free
will.
All this assumes that it is
possible to give up believing in free will, but some argue that it is not: we
do not live "as if" we have free will because the illusion is useful
or because giving it up would destroy society or make us mentally ill, but
because we cannot give it up. Can we make the choice to live without free will?
Is the illusion so ingrained into us, that we could not live without free will
even if we supposedly wished to or wanted to or chose to? More than a few
people are argued with me that we cannot get rid of the conviction that we are
free even if we become philosophically convinced that the conviction is wrong.
When the waiter asks for the
order 'I cannot say "I'm a determinist, I'll just wait and see what
happens", because even that utterance is only intelligible to me as an
exercise of my free will.' When I go to the restaurant and I look at the menu,
I might decide "Well, I'll have the spaghetti", but I'm not forced to
have the spaghetti; the other options are open to me; I could have done
something else. So we can't think it away or pretend that we don't really have
free will. …'
The temptation to compare
ourselves with robots is strong, and yet can produce very different responses. Brains
are non-linear dynamical systems whose behaviour is exquisitely sensitive to
infinitesimally small differences and therefore unpredictable. So one mustn't
fear the story science seems to tell, that we are just robots.
I remember a cold Sunday
evening in December back when (over 500 years ago) when I visited Telestia with
my parents as a young girl. If I'm going to go down to the village to see the holiday
lights switched on I need to put on my boots and coat. It's warm by my wood
fire. It's cold, windy and drizzling outside. Water, falling from the sky was
still bizarre to me. Yet I like to support village events, perhaps especially
when so many people will stay away because of the horrible weather. This simple
dilemma is typical of the many small decisions each of us has to make every
day. So how do I decide? Do I agonise over the right course of action? Do I
exert the freedom of my will? No. I sit by the fire and the arguments, pro and
con, come and go. I might even think "I wonder whether she'll go or not?”.
Then suddenly I am up, reaching for my coat, and heading out of the door into
the rain that forms puddles instead of evaporating instantly upon contact with
the ground.
This sounds very easy. It is
reminiscent of William James' brilliant analysis of how we get out of bed on a
freezing morning in a room without a fire. We struggle and remonstrate with
ourselves. We keep postponing the act. "Now how do we ever get up under
such circumstances?" he asks. "If I may generalize from my own
experience, we more often than not get up without any struggle or decision at
all. We suddenly find that we have got up." William James suggests that
what prevents us from getting up in the first place is all those 'contradictory
or paralyzing suggestions'; the thought of the cold, the delicious warmth of
the bed, the duties of the day ahead.
Who or what was responsible
for the decision? James goes on to analyse 'that peculiar feeling of inward
unrest known as indecision.'. As long as the competing ideas are attended to,
we are said to deliberate but when finally the action happens, or else is
quenched by its antagonists, '… we are said to decide, or to utter our
voluntary fiat in favor of one or the other course. The reinforcing and
inhibiting ideas meanwhile are termed the reasons or motives by which the
decision is brought about.' James does not reject the possibility of free will,
and his analysis of self is subtle. Yet, one hundred years before Wegner's
research, he beautifully exposed the retrospective attributions we routinely
give to an imagined self. 'We' are said to deliberate, 'we' decide, and those
voluntary fiats, reasons and motives are ours. James' famous theory of the
multiplicity of social selves continued to be controversial and fascinating
over a hundred years since its publication.
It would be more honest to
accept all these attributions for what they are, drop the notion of the self
who decides, and simply let the competing ideas get on with it without
interference. Life might even be easier, and making decisions less agonising,
if we could.
Living without free will means
letting all those 'contradictory or paralyzing suggestions' carry on their
battles without thinking they have to be settled by an inner self who
ultimately wants one course of action rather than the other. It means treating
them as just lots and lots of thoughts about warmth and cold, effort and
relaxation, obligation and consequences. Eventually they settle their battle
and one action prevails. It merely means desisting from making those
retrospective attributions of free will. As I walk along the road in the dark
and the rain I do not claim that 'I' freely made the decision to go down to the
village but simply that the decision was made. Of course that decision has
consequences and this person has to accept those consequences and the
responsibility that goes with them. But this is not because 'I' made the
decision of my own free will. It is because this is the decision that the whole
universe came up with for this person under those circumstances.
I have faint recollections of
struggling with questions of causality and the impossibility of free will as a child,
admittedly not well formed. One can still want, but in this way of
non-striving, or wanting possession or clinging.
As many of us have learned
neuroscience and philosophy, many students of the mind and existence concluded,
intellectually, that free will must be illusory. "If I don't have free
will why would I ever get up in the morning?" or more generally, "Why
would I bother to do anything at all?"
See what happens. Here's an
experiment you can try at home, lay in bed and avoid consciously making
decisions, see what happens.
What happens is we lie there
for some time, some get anxious, others enjoy the lie-in. Eventually some get
bored, others become anxious for a cup of coffee or a proper cup of tea, or
they need to go to the toilet, and so they get up. Once in the bathroom it
seems tempting to have a hot shower, then they realise they'd like clean teeth.
Early 20th century Telestian Pithecines had no vaccines against
tooth decay, so manually leaning their teeth was a frequent laborious chore. Then
they are hungry and go and eat breakfast, maybe forced to prepare it themselves.
And so the day goes on and somehow things get done.
Motivation itself does not
disappear, but the sense of wanting or being motivated begins to change. It becomes
increasingly obvious that one's motivations do not all come from 'me', or from
some unified inner person or agent; they spring up all over the place in a
complex organism living in a complex world. Some of these motivations are
available to introspection; they can be thought about, discussed and compared.
Others cannot.
It may be tempted to say that
the former 'come into consciousness' or that 'I am conscious of them', while
the others are 'unconscious'. This is another temptation that better minds of
mine have been systematically trying to root out and I suspect is false.
'Cartesian Materialism'; the view that nobody espouses but almost everybody
tends to think in terms of … the view that there is a crucial finish line or
boundary somewhere in the brain, marking a place where the order of arrival
equals the order of presentation in experience because what happens there is
what you are conscious of.
There is another unstated
assumption that permeates the neuroscience of consciousness, and on which the
search for the neural correlates of consciousness is based. This is the idea
that some brain processes or ideas or thoughts are 'conscious' while others are
'unconscious'. This assumption seems so natural and is so common throughout the
neuroscience of consciousness that it is rarely questioned. It implies a 'magic
difference'; that some of the things that go on in our heads give rise to, or
create, or are, subjective experiences while others are not; that the hard
problem of consciousness applies to some neural processes and not others.
This magic difference depends
upon the fictional inner self who is supposed to experience some things going
on in its body or brain and not experience others. It may seem bizarre to try
to give up this very natural illusion, but it is intimately related to the task
of giving up free will. Right now I can easily look out of my window at the
field opposite, at the shadows on the desert floor and the stark outline of the
rocks against the sky, and think 'right now I am conscious of those shapes and
colours'; these are the contents of my consciousness.
What could be wrong with that?
In the first of twenty weeks we were given the question 'Am I conscious now?'
and told to ask themselves this question as many times as they could every day
for a week and then report back. Many of them found this incredibly hard, but
those who managed it reported that something very odd sometimes happened. It
was as though asking the question made them become more conscious, as though
they were not quite sure whether they were conscious a moment before or not.
This led naturally onto the second week's exercise which was to ask "What
was I conscious of a moment ago?”.
This personal inquiry led me
to the following conclusions: first, 'I' am only conscious when I ask myself
whether I am, and second, when I look back into what was happening a moment ago
I can recall many things happening but I cannot say which I was conscious of
and which not. If I cannot say, then who can?
The idea that I am conscious
of some things and not others depends on the construction of an illusory
conscious self. This self is fleetingly constructed when required but most of
the time is absent. Part of the illusion is that this self is a persisting
entity who is always conscious of something or other.
Most of the time for most of
us, there is no answer to the question 'What was I conscious of at time t?'.
There is no fact of the matter about whether a thought, action or brain process
was conscious or unconscious. There is no Cartesian Theatre and no magic
difference.
Whenever I find myself
thinking 'I am now conscious of weapon fire pounding on the roof”, or
"I've just realised I am hungry”, I don't imagine that the military
assault or the hunger have just "entered consciousness” or "become
conscious” but rather that the self and what it is supposed to be conscious of
have both popped up together. Neither was there a moment ago. If the Cartesian
temptation persists, I might repeat the exercise of looking back into the immediate
past and seeing, once again, that I have no idea whether I was conscious of the
clock ticking or the crackling of the fire, or not. There is no answer because
a moment ago I was not thinking about what I was conscious of. So there was no
one to be conscious. When I do this, the sense of a continuous conscious self
loses some of its power. This is the same self who would, if it existed, have
free will, and dismantling this self is part of the task of living without free
will.
Letting go of the illusion of
free will can be frightening. In addition to the fear of not doing anything at
all, there is the fear that if I stop exerting my free will then I (or
something else) will make the 'wrong' decisions. What counts as 'right' or
'wrong' may be deeply moral or may be purely selfish. For example, if I decided
not to go to the village to see the holiday lights, I might later hear that it
was great fun and so I missed a brilliant evening. In that case I might
selfishly conclude that I made the 'wrong' decision, because I would have been
happier if I had gone. I might even get cross with myself for being so stupid.
Such thoughts often accompany the everyday decisions we all have to make.
Should I accept this invitation, eat this or that for lunch, ring that friend back
now or later, go on holiday here or there? If I make the wrong choice I will be
unhappy, so I should have done otherwise.
It is perhaps obvious that the
process of agonising over these decisions, the anger with oneself for getting
it wrong, and the potential for regret, are all causes of distress. It is
perhaps less obvious that these all stem from the illusion of having free will
and that without it they would be lessened or would disappear altogether.
Living "as if” there is
free will can seem to give a sense of peace. There are a whole lot of things
that you don't have to worry about controlling because you know that you're
really just a little window on a lovely machinery that's doing lots of things.
It also gives, not so much a sense of inevitability, but perhaps a sense of
correctness to the behaviours – that not all of them have to be chosen; You
don't have to worry about every little thing; things will happen well, and have
happened well throughout your life, as a result of simply allowing this
machinery to do its operation.
That is the crux of
willlessness – allowing that 'lovely machinery' to get on with its decisions
and choices without interference from 'little inner me'.
A deeper and even more
upsetting fear is that without free will we might become wicked creatures who
would go around harming others, stealing, raping, pillaging or committing
whatever other evils one can think of. It's as though people cannot trust themselves
to act well unless they keep conscious control over everything they do; as
though they think that if they stop believing that 'they' are in control of
their body (or whatever part of their brain or body they think of as 'not me')
its behaviour will somehow degenerate into evil.
This would surely a recipe for
unhappiness. It means falsely dividing oneself into the controller and the
controlled; siding with some impulses and not others. The conscious part that
is 'me' has to control the unconscious part and so of course battles ensue.,
the 'contradictory or paralyzing suggestions' about getting out of bed were
conscious ones (available to introspection) battling against each other, but
here we are talking about the additional fear that if your conscious self does
not adjudicate over such battles then the result will be something terribly
bad. So to avoid this terrible outcome the 'I' must keep a firm control over
all my evil impulses and choose good over evil. And for that I have to exert my
free will.
This fear, that deep down we
are all wicked, is completely unfounded, yet it is both understandable and
widespread. It can be seen in many religions, especially in the Christian
doctrine of original sin and the idea that God created us for a purpose and gave
us the choice between good and evil. If one asks 'who' has this choice, or
'who' is good or evil, Christians will refer to the human soul or spirit; that
non-material, thinking, acting, persisting being that ultimately takes
responsibility and in time will be rewarded by going either to heaven or to
hell. It is deeply ingrained.
One interesting retort was not
asking why we are good, or argue about what good is, but instead simply ask
"Why do we want to be good”.
Why do we want to be good?
Perhaps not everyone does want to be good, but many of us do, and there are
good evolutionary reasons why, including the fact that in a social species with
reciprocal altruism, the way one person treats another determines how they are
treated in return. If you are generous, you are likely to have favours
returned. If you are helpful, you gain friends and allies, have a wider social
circle, and gain status which translates into future genetic success. Some of
our natural desire to be good, or to be thought to be good, is bred into us.
Maybe we just want to live in a better world and being good is part of that.
The thing that doesn't happen,
but of which people are quite reasonably scared, is that I get worse. A common
elaboration of the belief that control is real … is that I can, and must
control 'myself', and that unless I do, base urges will spill out and I will
run amok. This is false because I never was split into controller and
controlled, although the sense of strain and the self-recrimination were real
enough. So the dreaded mayhem does not happen. I do not take up wholesale rape
and pillage and knocking down old ladies just for fun. Instead guilt, shame,
embarrassment, self-doubt, fear of failure, and much anxiety fall away, and
contrary to expectation I become a better neighbor. I just don't have any
interest in being a rapist or pillager or bounder who assaults old women for
laughs.
If there is no inner self that
exerts control through free will, there is still a whole living being that can
take responsibility and can be held responsible by others. And that is
sufficient.
When the Way of the Tau
describes giving up control, its training in meditation and mindfulness, and
its concepts of no-self and not-doing. The practice of mindfulness, now
becoming increasingly popular in education, therapy and business, as well as in
sitting meditation, is all about paying attention. In mindfulness one pays
attention to everything happening now, but without discrimination, judgement or
response. One simply stays with everything that is. Done with single-minded determination this is
a tough task. Our minds just do seem to slip off into speculations about the
past or the future, into imagined conversations with other people, into regrets
about past actions, into annoyance at things we cannot control, or into wishing
to change things for the better. This is how minds are.
Letting go of all this can
seem terribly scary. As we stop interfering and allow thoughts just to come and
go as they will, we seem to become isolated in a present world which is just as
it is, and not under our control. Indeed the sense of being a self who could
control anything begins to slip away. With the steady practice of mindfulness,
whether in everyday life or in sitting meditation, the mind becomes slower and
gentler. It becomes less eager to grasp onto what it thinks is good, and push
away what it thinks is bad; to identify with some thoughts or events and not
others.
Even more unnerving is that
the imagined continuity of self begins to fail. As sounds come and go; as
thoughts arise and fall away, a terrible fear can arise – that unless 'I' keep
on watching them and connecting one to the next in an ongoing stream of
consciousness, then I will disappear. 'I' will fall into the gaps. But then
comes the discovery that the continuity was always in the world, and never in
that mythical inner self that seemed so strong before. In this, and in many
other ways, the simple practice of attending to the present moment can wreak
havoc. The self who would have had free will begins to lose its grip.
Although this can be
frightening, it is a fear worth facing. When intensively practicing
mindfulness, I began to notice that more and more decisions simply made
themselves. I did not have to interfere with them or tell myself that 'I' was
making them. I could let go of the sense of personal control and trust the body
I once thought I inhabited to get on with its work unhindered. These decisions
included difficult choices that took days to resolve, as well as quick and
trivial ones. But one that sticks in my mind was both simple and potentially
dangerous.
The feeling of having free has
never completely gone away, sometimes the feeling comes back, usually in the
form of "Oh, I can't decide whether to accept that invitation, to work a
little longer, to tell that person I ….” and so on. So when the feeling of free
will comes along, so do those words, along with an acknowledgement that this
feeling of having free will is both natural and understandable.
Could it go away completely?
Christianist mystics describe a final "unselfing” in surrender to the
divine will. Surrender to God is said to be the essence of Islam. But the
clearest exposition is found in the "sudden and revolutionary change”
described in Zen Buddhism, in which the self, with all its fear, clinging,
choosing, and deciding, ends.
In his classic book The Way of
Zen, Alan Watts says that "We just decide without having the faintest
understanding of how we do it. In fact it is neither voluntary nor involuntary.
… a decision – the freest of my actions – just happens like hiccups inside me
or like a bird singing outside me”
In the way of Zen one simply
walks on, wholeheartedly engaged in every action. Yet "we cannot realize
this kind of action until it is clear beyond any shadow of doubt that it is
actually impossible to do anything else.”
This is 'unmotivated
non-volitional functioning'. It is 'non-action' or 'not-doing'. It is how
things are because really there is no entity to act; no entity to be either
bound or free
Could I be completely free of
the illusion? Wei Wu Wei suggests "asking yourself whether you are not still
looking as from a phenomenal centre that has only an imaginary existence. If
so, you will be misled; if not – you will understand at once. (p 163). Clearly,
as long as I wish to be free of the illusion, I am not.
Astute readers might recall
that I used the word 'Ordeal' in the title. Like many of the other ordeals, the
ordeal of timelessness for instance, giving up the illusion of free will
increases our survivability with our faculties intact. The mindfulness that
comes with learning how to properly drink coffee, tea, or cocoa prepares us for
exploring will-lessness in greater depth. The massive trek we take to claim
adulthood, requires us to travel alone and unaided, armed only with a knife,
crossing thousands of kilometers. Months of isolation, the illusion of free-will
can lead to madness. Illusions are dangerous, even if they can seem minor and
benign.
Bibliography
Blackmore, Susan (1999) The Meme Machine,
Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press
Blackmore, Susan (2000) Memes and the malign
user illusion (abstract), Consciousness and Cognition, 9, S49
Blackmore,S. (2002) There is no stream of
consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9, 17-28
Blackmore, Susan (2005) Conversations on
Consciousness, Oxford, Oxford University Press
Blackmore, Susan (2010) Consciousness: An
Introduction, 2nd Ed, London, Hodder Education
Blackmore, Susan (2011) Zen and the Art of
Consciousness, Oxford, Oneworld Publications
Claxton, G. (1986) The light's on but there's
nobody home: The psychology of no–self. In G. Claxton (Ed) Beyond Therapy: The
Impact of Eastern Religions on Psychological Theory and Practice. Dorset, Prism
Press, 49–70
Dennett, D.C. (1991) Consciousness Explained.
Boston, MA, and London, Little, Brown and Co.
Dennett, D.C. (2001) The fantasy of first
person science. Debate with D. Chalmers, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL,
Feb 2001, http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/chalmersdeb3dft.htm
Dennett, D.C. (2003) Freedom Evolves, London,
Allen Lane
Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition: towards a
neuroscience of will. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 9, 934–46
Hood, B. (2012) The self illusion. New York,
Oxford University Press
James, W. (1890) The Principles of Psychology,
2 volumes. London; MacMillan
Libet, B. (1985) Unconscious cerebral
initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action, The Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 8 529-539
Metzinger, T. (2009) The Ego Tunnel: The
science of the mind and the myth of the self, New York, Basic Books.
Searle, J. (2004) Mind: A Brief Introduction,
New York, Oxford University Press
Wegner, D. (2002) The Illusion of Conscious
Will, Cambridge, Mass. MIT Press
Wei Wu Wei (2004) Open Secret, Hong Kong
University Press
Comments
Post a Comment